The
Unexpected Departure
The Axelrod upper equilibrium
requires certain conditions. One of them is that the expected number of plays
be great enough; another is that the play not end at too definite at time. If
it does, then a “backwards induction paradox” destroys the Axelrod truce, no
matter how long the tournament.
Consider the following scene:
Curly is about to play with Moe
in a dilemma tournament sceduled to last exactly 100 rounds. Curly, a Silver
Rule player, is optimistic that he can convince Moe (an Iron Rule player) that
it’ll be in his own best interest to cooperate.
But Moe said, “What about the
100th round? Won’t that be the last one?”
Curly said, “Yes.”
“There won’t be any after the
100th?”
“Yes,” said Curly.
Moe asked, “So in the very last
play, what’s to keep me from defecting?”
“‘Cause I’ll defect the next...”
Curly said, then slapped himself on the face. “Alright, nothing will stop you
from defecting on the 100th play.”
“So you might as well defect too,
right?” Moe said, smiling.
“I guess so,” Curly said
reluctantly. “On the 100th play.”
Moe continued, “And what about
the 99th play? What’s to keep me from defecting then?”
“‘Cause I’ll defect the next...”
Curly said, then slapped himself on the face. “But I’ll defect on the 100th
play anyhow.”
“That’s right,” Moe said,
smiling.
“So nothing’s keeping you from
defecting on the 99th play.”
“That’s right,” Moe said,
smiling.
“So I should defect on the 99th
play also,” said Curly.
“That’s right,” Moe said. “Now,
what about the 98th play?”
And so they continued! Moe
whittled down Curly’s proposed truce, one play at a time, starting from the
end. By the time the conversation was over, Moe had convinced Curly that the
only logical course was for them to defect from each other 100 times, drawing
the tournament. And so they did; yet when Curly played with Larry (a Gold Rule
player) they cooperated 100 times, for a truce!
Thus we deduce, by mathematical
induction, that the prospect of abruptly terminated play, even if in the far
future, poisons the relationship at its inception. That is the “backwards
induction paradox”.
In dilemma play, cooperation requires
continuity to the end. Departure should not be at an expected time lest that
light the backwards-induction fuse; departure should be unannounced, at an
unexpected time.
We need an unexpected
departure; but this yields a paradox. Consider this following story about an
Unexpected Exam:
Once upon a time a professor told
his students, “Sometime next week I will give you an exam; and that exam will
be at an unexpected time. Right up until the moment I give you the exam, you
will have no way to deduce when it will happen, or even if it will happen. It
will be an Unexpected Exam.”
One of the professor’s students
objected, “But then the exam couldn’t happen on Friday; for by then it would be
expected!”
The professor said, “True.”
The student continued, “So
Friday’s ruled out.”
Another student said, “But if
Thursday’s the last possible day for an Unexpected Exam, then it’s ruled out
too; for by Thursday the Thursday exam will be expected!”
The professor said, “True.”
And so on; by such steps the
students concluded that the Unexpected Exam can’t happen on Friday, Thursday,
Wednesday, Tuesday, or Monday; so it can’t happen at all!
“So you don’t expect it?” said
the professor.
His students said, “No!”
The professor smiled...
The next Wednesday, he handed out
an exam, to the students’ surprise.
That’s the Paradox of the
Unexpected Exam. This also is a backwards induction paradox; but this time
it is a strangely false result rather than a strangely undesirable
result. This match suggests the following fable.
The same professor visited the
Dean; he said, “I will depart this school sometime during the next month. To
ensure cordial relations between us until that time, my departure will take
place on an unexpected day.”
The Dean retorted, “You couldn’t
leave on the 31st, for by then your Unexpected Departure would be expected.”
The professor agreed.
The Dean added, “Having ruled out
the 31st, the 30th is also ruled out; for it would be expected.”
The professor agreed to that too.
And so the conversation
continued; and in the end the Dean concluded, “Your Unexpected Departure can’t
happen on any day. Therefore I don’t expect it.” The professor agreed.
On the seventeenth day of the
month the professor departed, to the Dean’s astonishment.
This Paradox of the Unexpected
Departure is just what the doctor ordered; for here the failure of
backwards induction (so puzzling to the reason) is precisely what is needed to
defend the Axelrod equilibrium from its backwards induction proof!
Above I insisted that dilemma
tournaments use “open bounding”; that is, replay only if a random device
permits it. This ensures an Unexpected Departure; play will be finite, but
there will be no definite last play during which the Iron player is safe from
the danger of Silver retaliation.
The conclusion then is clear; let
none of your social relationships end too definitely; let there be some
possibility that you might encounter that person again, soon. (And conversely,
when you must leave, slip away quietly!)
No comments:
Post a Comment